Back to the Philosophy 101 Home Page
Back to Main Lecture Notes Page
Lecture Notes: November 18
References herein to Hume's work are via page numbers in the Hackett.
Hume makes a distinction
between matters of fact and relations of ideas (p
15)
Relations of ideas are an exception to his empiricist rule that every object
of knowledge must trace back to sense impressions.
'Matters of fact' are a posteriori, and contingent.
(Be careful not
to confuse Hume's use of this term with our current idiom.)
'Relations of
ideas' are a priori, and necessary.
We can demonstrate relations of ideas using the law of contradiction (p 11)
If the denial of a statement leads to a contradiction, the original statement must be true.
Earlier we called
this 'proof by reductio ad absurdum'.
Examples of contradictions:
'p and not-p', for any proposition p
'x = not-x', for any object x
Hume says that we can generate mathematical (and logical) truths using such proofs.
These require
no empirical support, or justification.
Compare Hume's position with Descartes'.
Descartes called a priori propositions 'innate ideas' and extended the range of these ideas.
For Descartes, anything we know has to be derived from pure reason.
This included all knowledge of the physical world.
Hume accepts this sort of reasoning (he calls it demonstrative) but limits its range to logic and mathematics.
Knowledge of the physical world will have to arise exclusively from the senses.
Review the items listed in Part I of the handout. (See
Nov. 11)
1-4 are all matters of fact, trace to impressions.
5 is a relation of ideas, whose denial is a contradiction.
What about the last three? - Are they relations of ideas?
Compare A) 2+2=5; and B) the sun won't rise tomorrow.
Consider the difference between the reasons that each are wrong.
A) is false because
of the way the terms are related.
B) is still possible; we can't have certainty that it's false. (See p 22)
We can't find out B) is wrong by mere process of thought.
Hume would call 6) and 7) matters of fact, since we learn them via inductive
reasoning on sense experience.
How about 8)?
Compare to 'all bachelors are unmarried'.
This we might say is 'analytically' true, and so is a relation of ideas.
It's the meanings of the terms which make the statement true.
It's a truth which arises from the logic of the language.
So 6) and 7), and all scientific laws, are matters of fact.
Are they true
matters of fact?
Hume argues that we don't know these, because empiricism can't establish the
truth of laws of nature (p 19).
The "secret powers" (the connections) are hidden from us.
Effects are distinct from their causes (p 17).
We have no experience of the cause.
We only see the conjunctions of certain events.
Consider unknown objects: we can not reason to their natures, but only learn
from experience of them.
So, all beliefs about the world are based on experience, and experience only
tells us what was, not what has to be.
That is, we have no access to the causes.
So we have no access to the laws of nature.
How do we know that the sun will rise tomorrow?
We can't.
It's not about a big (law-like) explosion of the sun, but our inability to project
from past experience into the future.
This is generally known as the Problem of Induction: How do we get knowledge
of the unobserved?
Induction is how you know 6, 7, and how the person next to you has a beating
heart
Hume's Skeptical argument about induction:
1) Our beliefs about future events and unobserved objects are matters of fact.
2) Beliefs about matters of fact are based on experience.
3) Experience tells us how things were, not how they will be.
:. Our beliefs about the future and the unobserved are uncertain.
For example, consider billiard balls:
1) I have seen one ball strike another many times.
2) Each time the ball which was struck has moved, motion was transferred.
:. The struck ball will move this time.
But the conclusion
doesn't follow.
What more do we need?
We can add, as
a third premise, the principle of the uniformity of nature (PUN): The future
will resemble the past. (See p 22)
This would render the argument valid, but what
could justify the PUN?
We have no basis for inference.
We can't, for
example, bootstrap: claim that it is itself inductively justified.
Yet all inductive inference presupposes it.
If we had knowledge of cause and effect relations, we could establish the PUN.
But we only have
experience of constant conjunction, not the connections. (See p 46)
We can't find effects in causes.
So why do we believe the connection?
Why do we exit through the door, not the window?
We do feel like we have the connections but this is just habit (p 50)
We make a mental leap, unjustified by evidence.
Consider the man suddenly brought into world. (p 27-8)
It is only experience which gives us knowledge of matters of fact, and this can only provide knowledge of past events, and can not justify the PUN.
Back to Main Lecture Notes Page